康德的先天綜合判斷及一種反駁
? Why Kant wants to establish the existence of synthetic a priori truths?
Kant』s reasoning of synthetic a priori truths (SAP)
In the Introduction of CPR, Kant objects to the view of the sources of
knowledge by Leibniz and Hume. Both of them regard our knowledge as dividedinto 2 fundamental types – necessary and a priori knowledge, and contingent anda posteriori knowledge. Kant』s new distinction – analytic/synthetic – is
independent from these older distinctions. A judgement is analytic ifthe predicate is contained in and thought in the concept of the subject. E.g.『a triangle has three sides』 is analytic because the concept of three-sidednessis contained in that of triangularity and its negation is contradictory. Ajudgement is synthetic if the predicate that it connects with theconcept of the subject is not contained or thought in it. The judgement must betrue by virtue of something other than the principle of contradiction: it restson a 『synthesis』. E.g. 『All bodies are heavy [have weight]』is synthetic becausethe concept of weight is not contained in that of body and is added to itthrough experience. Hence synthetic judgements extend our knowledge, as analytic
judgements cannot.For L and H, they would expect all necessary and a priori judgements
to be analytic, and all contingent and empirical judgements to be synthetic. ButKant argues that not all necessary and a priori judgements are analytic.Metaphysical judgements are a priori (ap) and synthetic. E.g. 『every event hasa cause』. Because it』s necessary, it must be ap. But it』s not analytic, for theconcept of an event doesn』t contain that of being an effect. This judgement is thusinformative and synthetic, whilst being ap. Metaphysical judgements thus can』tbe derived from either logic or experience. This means that the question 『ismetaphysics possible』 can be answered positively only if the question 『are sap
judgments possible』 can be answered positively.He goes on to argue that mathematical and geometrical judgements are not
analytic but synthetic instead. Consider the judgement 『7+5=12』. If 「7+5=12」 isanalytic, then 「12」 must be contained in 「7+5」. But the concept of 7+5 doesn』tcontain the concept of 12. Synthesis is required. The truth of 7 + 5 = 12 canonly be established through an intuition, that is, if we want to check thetruth of this claim we need to appeal to an aid, like our fingers. It』s anappeal to experience, but not an appeal to any particular experience. The same is true forgeometrical judgments. 「A straight line is the shortest distance between twopoints」 is synthetic because the concept of straightness doesn』t contain any
information regarding the relative lengths of different lines joining twopoints. We cannot extract the quantitative predicate 「shortest」 from theconcept 「straight line」 because 「straight line」 is a purely qualitative concept.In order to establish the truth of the proposition, we must also appeal tointuition.Mathematics and geometry
show that it is possible to have knowledge which is necessary but not logicallynecessary, so there』s a reason for thinking that metaphysical knowledge, whichlays claim to the same status, may equally be possible. K thus undermines L』sclaim that knowledge of reality is derivable from logical principles, and opens
the door to demonstrating, against Hume, the possibility of metaphysics.Analysing Kant』s reasoning
Some people argue that
『mathematics is synthetic』 is defensible, but 『geometry is a priori』 isdubious: geometry is now divided into pure geometry, which consists of formalsystems based on axioms for which truth is not claimed, and which areconsequently not synthetic, and applied geometry, a branch of physics, thetruth of which is determined empirically, and which is therefore not a priori. Thequestion is, then, what difference is made to the claims of the Introduction ifKant』s claims about either mathematics or geometry are rejected. If Kant, in
the Introduction, assumes that mathematics and geometry are not open to repudiation,this might suggest that their truth is premised in this context and thus in theCritique as a whole. The whole C might be undermined.However, Gardner argues
that there』s a clear statement in the Critique of Practical Reason that Kantdoes not regard the truths of geometry and mathematics as beyond skepticaldoubt and so cannot be operating this strategy. There he says that Hume onlyfailed to extend skeptical doubt to mathematical and geometrical truths becausehe mistakenly regarded their propositions as analytic, and that once it is realizedthat they are synthetic, it becomes possible to doubt their alleged necessity,
and indeed that empiricism demands such skepticism. Furthermore, Kant goes onto describe himself as having followed in the Critique the strategy of firstdisposing of the empiricism witnessed in Hume』s critique of causation, and thenoverthrowing its inevitable consequence, skepticism, first, in natural scienceand, then, in mathematics.The Critique is intended,
therefore, to secure rather than assume the truth of geometry and mathematics.Kant』s justification of the metaphysics of experience belongs to the sameproject as that which adds to the defense ofmathematics and geometry, but it does not draw on their epistemological
prestige, and the Critique is not undermined by any defects in Kant』s accountof mathematics or geometry. (This interpretation is substantiated by thediscussion of methodology in the Prolegomena. Kant says that he isproceeding in this expository work on the basis that mathematics, geometry andeven natural science are objectively valid, because he is following a differentmethodology from the Critique, one that is analytical or regressive, ratherthan synthetical or progressive. Analytical enquiry rests upon somethingalready known as trustworthy, from which we can set out with confidence andascend to sources as yet unknown, the discovery of which will explain to uswhat we already knew. The synthetical method, which he follows in the Critique,
is based on no data except reason itself.)Thus if the appeal to mathematics and geometry is restricted, Kant may still claim to have clarified the problem set by metaphysics, and the central line of argument in the Critique will remain untouched.
推薦閱讀:
※張志偉/馬麗:問題與對話:一種非黑格爾式的哲學史觀
※重磅丨吳國盛:我們都在誤解科學!
※陳思和:文學滋養我們的靈魂
※史上最牛的西方哲學史筆記【完整版(中)】
※如何優雅地扒下哲學家的褲子?
TAG:哲學 | 康德ImmanuelKant | 哲學史 |